Some have proposed a model of divine foreknowledge which allows them to avoid
the dilemma of affirming either that God creates people for the purpose of
sending them to hell (Calvinism) or that he creates them without certain
knowledge of their fate (open theism). In this alternative view God knows that
certain individuals will be damned but cannot on this basis refrain from
creating them. This is called “simple foreknowledge,” for it holds that God
simply knows what will take place but cannot alter it in the light of this
knowledge. The fact that God foreknows what will occur does not increase his
control over what occurs.
This view is somewhat different from the classical Arminian position, in
which divine foreknowledge was understood to increase God’s control over what
transpires without denying human freedom. The original disagreement between
Arminius and Calvinistic contemporaries concerned whether God predestines the
elect on the basis of his foreknowledge of their faith, as Arminius held, or
foreknows the elect on the basis of his having predestined them. The Arminian
position presupposes that God acts responsively to his foreknowledge. Thus, he
foreknows who will believe and then predestines them.
The simple foreknowledge position denies that God can respond to his
foreknowledge in this way, thus avoiding the problem of God creating individuals
he knows will go to hell. In this view, God’s act of creating people is not
affected by his knowledge of what will become of them. It is as though God
possesses “insider information” but must buy and sell as thought he did not. For
the same reason, this view does not require divine reason behind every event
that occurs. God eternally foreknows each particular evil that will ever take
place, but he can do nothing about it.
There are a few problems with this view. First, this and every other version
of the Exhaustively Definite Foreknowledge doctrine cannot adequately account
for the many passages of Scripture that depict God as facing a partly open
future. Indeed, in one respect the simple foreknowledge perspective fares worse
than classical Arminianism or Calvinism. Whenever Scripture emphasizes God’s
foreknowledge of future events, it is to exalt his sovereign control over what
is to come, which is exactly what the open view promotes.
Second, while the simple foreknowledge position avoids some difficulties by
denying that God can alter his behavior in response to his knowledge of the
future, it invites other difficulties. How can God respond to anything? With all
Christians, defenders of simple foreknowledge want to affirm that God sometimes
intervenes to bring about events that are more in line with his will. But if God
can’t alter the future that he knows is coming, how can he respond to this same
future when it becomes present? In the simple foreknowledge view, God must first
experience events in the present as though he had no foreknowledge and then
foreknow what he experienced and how he responded. In other words, his
foreknowledge functions as a sort of “hindsight.”
One might be inclined to pity God if this is his predicament. From all
eternity he has seen what is coming—the cosmic war, the horror, the pain, the
suffering, the unending plight of the damned. And he can even foresee how he
will respond to these tragedies once they occur. But he cannot do anything ahead
of time to avoid them. He’s hopelessly locked into an unending vision he can do
nothing about.
Third, this understanding of divine foreknowledge is irrelevant. In this
view, God’s exhaustive foreknowledge doesn’t make any practical difference for
God or for us concerning the flow of history. Everything proceeds as thought God
did not possess Exhaustively Definite Foreknowledge. Indeed, if we hold to the
pragmatic criterion of truth and insist that a belief must be able to make a
conceivable difference in life to be meaningfully affirmed, then simple
foreknowledge must be dismissed.
—Adapted from Satan and the Problem of Evil, pages 88-90
No comments :
Post a Comment